Our panel of 91 professional philosophers has responded to

284
 questions about 
Mind
81
 questions about 
Identity
208
 questions about 
Science
27
 questions about 
Gender
2
 questions about 
Action
24
 questions about 
Suicide
5
 questions about 
Euthanasia
23
 questions about 
History
287
 questions about 
Language
69
 questions about 
Business
36
 questions about 
Literature
218
 questions about 
Education
68
 questions about 
Happiness
124
 questions about 
Profession
221
 questions about 
Value
117
 questions about 
Children
51
 questions about 
War
154
 questions about 
Sex
151
 questions about 
Existence
4
 questions about 
Economics
96
 questions about 
Time
75
 questions about 
Beauty
75
 questions about 
Perception
374
 questions about 
Logic
110
 questions about 
Biology
31
 questions about 
Space
88
 questions about 
Physics
89
 questions about 
Law
244
 questions about 
Justice
110
 questions about 
Animals
392
 questions about 
Religion
80
 questions about 
Death
67
 questions about 
Feminism
105
 questions about 
Art
54
 questions about 
Medicine
70
 questions about 
Truth
32
 questions about 
Sport
58
 questions about 
Punishment
1280
 questions about 
Ethics
282
 questions about 
Knowledge
574
 questions about 
Philosophy
134
 questions about 
Love
77
 questions about 
Emotion
2
 questions about 
Culture
34
 questions about 
Music
58
 questions about 
Abortion
43
 questions about 
Color
39
 questions about 
Race
170
 questions about 
Freedom

Question of the Day

Interesting question! I think you're right that there's something peculiar about this disjunctive syllogism:

(1) B v ~ B
(2) ~ B
(3) ~ B

You say that (2) must be the negation of (1)'s left disjunct rather than the assertion of (1)'s right disjunct, even though both of those are syntactically the same. You may find allies in those who distinguish between (i) denying or rejecting a proposition and (ii) asserting the proposition's negation. See Section 2.5 of this SEP entry.

But here's a different diagnosis. Although (1)-(3) is a valid argument, and even a valid instance of disjunctive syllogism, the argument is informally defective because premise (1) is superfluous: (1) isn't needed for the argument's validity. Furthermore, anyone justified in asserting (2) is thereby justified in asserting (3) without need of (1). This argument is similar:

(4) ~ B v B
(5) ~ ~ B
(6) B

The claim that (5) is the negation of (4)'s left disjunct is at least as plausible as the claim that (2) is the negation of (1)'s left disjunct. But maybe the better diagnosis is that (4)-(6) is informally defective because (4) is unnecessary for the argument's validity and unnecessary for rationally proceeding from (5) to (6).