Our panel of 91 professional philosophers has responded to

374
 questions about 
Logic
67
 questions about 
Feminism
58
 questions about 
Punishment
208
 questions about 
Science
110
 questions about 
Biology
34
 questions about 
Music
170
 questions about 
Freedom
134
 questions about 
Love
124
 questions about 
Profession
77
 questions about 
Emotion
284
 questions about 
Mind
105
 questions about 
Art
81
 questions about 
Identity
36
 questions about 
Literature
80
 questions about 
Death
244
 questions about 
Justice
110
 questions about 
Animals
4
 questions about 
Economics
69
 questions about 
Business
51
 questions about 
War
23
 questions about 
History
75
 questions about 
Beauty
24
 questions about 
Suicide
43
 questions about 
Color
117
 questions about 
Children
89
 questions about 
Law
58
 questions about 
Abortion
88
 questions about 
Physics
574
 questions about 
Philosophy
154
 questions about 
Sex
151
 questions about 
Existence
96
 questions about 
Time
27
 questions about 
Gender
1280
 questions about 
Ethics
2
 questions about 
Culture
282
 questions about 
Knowledge
287
 questions about 
Language
54
 questions about 
Medicine
5
 questions about 
Euthanasia
75
 questions about 
Perception
2
 questions about 
Action
39
 questions about 
Race
221
 questions about 
Value
32
 questions about 
Sport
218
 questions about 
Education
68
 questions about 
Happiness
392
 questions about 
Religion
31
 questions about 
Space
70
 questions about 
Truth

Question of the Day

Interesting question! I think you're right that there's something peculiar about this disjunctive syllogism:

(1) B v ~ B
(2) ~ B
(3) ~ B

You say that (2) must be the negation of (1)'s left disjunct rather than the assertion of (1)'s right disjunct, even though both of those are syntactically the same. You may find allies in those who distinguish between (i) denying or rejecting a proposition and (ii) asserting the proposition's negation. See Section 2.5 of this SEP entry.

But here's a different diagnosis. Although (1)-(3) is a valid argument, and even a valid instance of disjunctive syllogism, the argument is informally defective because premise (1) is superfluous: (1) isn't needed for the argument's validity. Furthermore, anyone justified in asserting (2) is thereby justified in asserting (3) without need of (1). This argument is similar:

(4) ~ B v B
(5) ~ ~ B
(6) B

The claim that (5) is the negation of (4)'s left disjunct is at least as plausible as the claim that (2) is the negation of (1)'s left disjunct. But maybe the better diagnosis is that (4)-(6) is informally defective because (4) is unnecessary for the argument's validity and unnecessary for rationally proceeding from (5) to (6).