Our panel of 91 professional philosophers has responded to

96
 questions about 
Time
75
 questions about 
Perception
221
 questions about 
Value
51
 questions about 
War
43
 questions about 
Color
68
 questions about 
Happiness
88
 questions about 
Physics
374
 questions about 
Logic
2
 questions about 
Culture
151
 questions about 
Existence
75
 questions about 
Beauty
134
 questions about 
Love
69
 questions about 
Business
32
 questions about 
Sport
23
 questions about 
History
81
 questions about 
Identity
24
 questions about 
Suicide
124
 questions about 
Profession
89
 questions about 
Law
284
 questions about 
Mind
208
 questions about 
Science
574
 questions about 
Philosophy
67
 questions about 
Feminism
27
 questions about 
Gender
5
 questions about 
Euthanasia
105
 questions about 
Art
218
 questions about 
Education
2
 questions about 
Action
110
 questions about 
Biology
58
 questions about 
Punishment
80
 questions about 
Death
34
 questions about 
Music
4
 questions about 
Economics
58
 questions about 
Abortion
31
 questions about 
Space
287
 questions about 
Language
244
 questions about 
Justice
170
 questions about 
Freedom
70
 questions about 
Truth
117
 questions about 
Children
282
 questions about 
Knowledge
154
 questions about 
Sex
54
 questions about 
Medicine
392
 questions about 
Religion
1280
 questions about 
Ethics
110
 questions about 
Animals
36
 questions about 
Literature
77
 questions about 
Emotion
39
 questions about 
Race

Question of the Day

Interesting question! I think you're right that there's something peculiar about this disjunctive syllogism:

(1) B v ~ B
(2) ~ B
(3) ~ B

You say that (2) must be the negation of (1)'s left disjunct rather than the assertion of (1)'s right disjunct, even though both of those are syntactically the same. You may find allies in those who distinguish between (i) denying or rejecting a proposition and (ii) asserting the proposition's negation. See Section 2.5 of this SEP entry.

But here's a different diagnosis. Although (1)-(3) is a valid argument, and even a valid instance of disjunctive syllogism, the argument is informally defective because premise (1) is superfluous: (1) isn't needed for the argument's validity. Furthermore, anyone justified in asserting (2) is thereby justified in asserting (3) without need of (1). This argument is similar:

(4) ~ B v B
(5) ~ ~ B
(6) B

The claim that (5) is the negation of (4)'s left disjunct is at least as plausible as the claim that (2) is the negation of (1)'s left disjunct. But maybe the better diagnosis is that (4)-(6) is informally defective because (4) is unnecessary for the argument's validity and unnecessary for rationally proceeding from (5) to (6).