Our panel of 91 professional philosophers has responded to

58
 questions about 
Abortion
244
 questions about 
Justice
31
 questions about 
Space
54
 questions about 
Medicine
134
 questions about 
Love
284
 questions about 
Mind
117
 questions about 
Children
69
 questions about 
Business
218
 questions about 
Education
39
 questions about 
Race
34
 questions about 
Music
32
 questions about 
Sport
43
 questions about 
Color
51
 questions about 
War
70
 questions about 
Truth
392
 questions about 
Religion
67
 questions about 
Feminism
282
 questions about 
Knowledge
88
 questions about 
Physics
287
 questions about 
Language
27
 questions about 
Gender
58
 questions about 
Punishment
75
 questions about 
Perception
80
 questions about 
Death
36
 questions about 
Literature
4
 questions about 
Economics
96
 questions about 
Time
5
 questions about 
Euthanasia
23
 questions about 
History
151
 questions about 
Existence
221
 questions about 
Value
2
 questions about 
Culture
170
 questions about 
Freedom
124
 questions about 
Profession
105
 questions about 
Art
374
 questions about 
Logic
1280
 questions about 
Ethics
2
 questions about 
Action
110
 questions about 
Animals
110
 questions about 
Biology
24
 questions about 
Suicide
89
 questions about 
Law
574
 questions about 
Philosophy
81
 questions about 
Identity
68
 questions about 
Happiness
208
 questions about 
Science
75
 questions about 
Beauty
154
 questions about 
Sex
77
 questions about 
Emotion

Question of the Day

Interesting question! I think you're right that there's something peculiar about this disjunctive syllogism:

(1) B v ~ B
(2) ~ B
(3) ~ B

You say that (2) must be the negation of (1)'s left disjunct rather than the assertion of (1)'s right disjunct, even though both of those are syntactically the same. You may find allies in those who distinguish between (i) denying or rejecting a proposition and (ii) asserting the proposition's negation. See Section 2.5 of this SEP entry.

But here's a different diagnosis. Although (1)-(3) is a valid argument, and even a valid instance of disjunctive syllogism, the argument is informally defective because premise (1) is superfluous: (1) isn't needed for the argument's validity. Furthermore, anyone justified in asserting (2) is thereby justified in asserting (3) without need of (1). This argument is similar:

(4) ~ B v B
(5) ~ ~ B
(6) B

The claim that (5) is the negation of (4)'s left disjunct is at least as plausible as the claim that (2) is the negation of (1)'s left disjunct. But maybe the better diagnosis is that (4)-(6) is informally defective because (4) is unnecessary for the argument's validity and unnecessary for rationally proceeding from (5) to (6).