Our panel of 91 professional philosophers has responded to

43
 questions about 
Color
80
 questions about 
Death
69
 questions about 
Business
77
 questions about 
Emotion
31
 questions about 
Space
151
 questions about 
Existence
221
 questions about 
Value
1280
 questions about 
Ethics
284
 questions about 
Mind
81
 questions about 
Identity
287
 questions about 
Language
54
 questions about 
Medicine
89
 questions about 
Law
5
 questions about 
Euthanasia
105
 questions about 
Art
574
 questions about 
Philosophy
4
 questions about 
Economics
75
 questions about 
Beauty
110
 questions about 
Animals
27
 questions about 
Gender
23
 questions about 
History
208
 questions about 
Science
218
 questions about 
Education
32
 questions about 
Sport
39
 questions about 
Race
2
 questions about 
Action
96
 questions about 
Time
70
 questions about 
Truth
36
 questions about 
Literature
88
 questions about 
Physics
67
 questions about 
Feminism
244
 questions about 
Justice
282
 questions about 
Knowledge
170
 questions about 
Freedom
2
 questions about 
Culture
154
 questions about 
Sex
58
 questions about 
Abortion
392
 questions about 
Religion
110
 questions about 
Biology
58
 questions about 
Punishment
117
 questions about 
Children
34
 questions about 
Music
51
 questions about 
War
68
 questions about 
Happiness
124
 questions about 
Profession
374
 questions about 
Logic
24
 questions about 
Suicide
75
 questions about 
Perception
134
 questions about 
Love

Question of the Day

Like my colleague, I agree that you've put your finger on a potential moral problem with necrophilia. However, I have a worry about the rest of his analysis. My colleague writes: "I think the more primordial objection to necrophilia is that most of us see the good of sexual intimacy as the loving union of two persons." I certainly don't disagree that this is a good of sexual intimacy, but aside from the question of whether it's the good, I have a different worry: even if the loving union of two people is the good of sexual intimacy, it wouldn't follow that other forms of sexual activity are morally suspect. The most obvious case is masturbation. I've never seen anything that struck me as a plausible argument that masturbation is wrong. A standard Catholic objection is that all sex acts should be "open to the possibility of procreation," as some Vatican documents put it. My own view is that this is bad as theology, and worse if one doesn't accept theological premises. Another objection is that it's a special case of using someone—oneself in this case— as a mere means, and thereby not respecting their humanity. I think the right reply is that people masturbate, among other reasons, because it feels good, and for the release it brings, and it's a highly implausible stretch to say that people who masturbate don't respect themselves. And so if there's something morally wrong with necrophilia apart from the possible consequences for the wishes of living people, we'll need a different account.

Suppose it turned out that the practice of necrophilia tended to undermine one's ability to form relationships (not necessarily just sexual relationships) with other people. Suppose it tended to desensitize people who practice it in ways that undermine their moral sensitivity. I don't know whether this is true, and I don't think my hunches are worth anything. But certain habits and practices surely do tend to diminish one's moral responses, and if necrophilia is one of them, that would be a problem. But I stress: I don't pretend to know that this is true.

Another potential problem is that someone seeking out the opportunity to have sex with a corpse may very well need to cross other boundaries just to bring the situation about—breaking into a morgue, for example.

My first thought when I read your question, however, wasn't about the moral wrongness of necrophilia but about what Aristotle called eudaimonia—with human flourishing. I wonder whether someone who practices necrophilia is likely to be stunted in other ways. It's not altogether easy to see necrophilia fitting into an otherwise thriving psychology. One again, I don't think my mere intuitions here are worth much, but it's hard simply to set those intuitions aside.

Indeed, I think that one objection to necrophelia would, indeed, be that this might involve the violation of the wishes of the one who has died, but of course we can imagine a case in which a person's dying wish is that someone sexually use their body after they have died. I think the more primordial objection to necrophelia is that most of us see the good of sexual intimacy as the loving union of two persons. After death, most of us think that the dead body is a corpse and no longer a person. In the sexual act, the living person is not having intercourse with Pat (non-gender specific name) but with Pat's remains.
A qualification may be in order: there are philosophers who are sometimes called animalists who entertain the view that at death you still exist as long as your body endures in tact. Personally, I think that reveals a problem with animalism. They wind up viewing death as a qualitative change, whereas (intuitively) most of us see death as a substantial change, e.g. in a funeral, you are not burying Pat, but Pat's corpse.